]>
Abstract
It is shown that a finite lattice is isomorphic to the interval between two Hausdorff topologies on some set if and only if is distributive. The corresponding results had previously been shown in ZFC for intervals between topologies and, assuming the existence of infinitely many measurable cardinals, for intervals between topologies. |
The collection of all topologies on a given set forms a lattice under inclusion, in which the meet of two topologies is their intersection, while the join is the topology with their union as a sub-basis. This lattice has been an object of study since it was first defined by Birkhoff [1]: see the survey article by Larsen and Andima, [4], for more details.
In this paper we are concerned with the local structure of this lattice. Specifically, we are looking at the problem of determining the finite lattices such that there exist some set and some (perhaps with some specific separation properties) such that the interval is isomorphic to .
This problem was solved for topologies and by Valent and Larson and Rosický: Valent and Larson [7] proved that any finite distributive lattice can be realized as an interval between topologies, and Rosický [5] proved that any finite interval between topologies must be distributive. Hence a finite lattice can be realized as such an interval if and only if it is distributive.
Of course, Rosický's result implies that every finite interval between Hausdorff topologies must be distributive. In this paper we will show that the converse is true. This result has already been shown by Good, McIntyre and Watson in [3]—indeed, the topologies and can be assumed to be —under the assumption of the existence of infinitely many measurable cardinals. In this paper we will make no set-theoretic assumptions beyond ZFC.
For a partially ordered set, let denote the set of down-closed subsets of , partially ordered by inclusion. For a finite lattice let denote the set of join-irreducible elements (i.e. elements such that is not the least element of the lattice and, if then or ). Recall that a finite lattice is distributive if and only if for some , which happens if and only if .
If is a family of subsets of a set with the finite intersection property, let denote the filter on which has as a filter subbasis. We will say that is compatible with if has the finite intersection property.
Let denote the least cardinal of a filter subbasis for a free ultrafilter on . It is easy to show that . For more details, and relationships between and other small cardinals, see [6]
If and are ultrafilters on sets and respectively, let denote the ultrafilter where . We define ultrafilters on for by , . Note that this product is associative: if , and are ultrafilters, then .
If is a topological space, then an o-filter on is a filter in the partial order of non-empty open sets of , and an o-ultrafilter is a maximal o-filter.
For a topology on and , let denote the neighbourhood filter at in the topology , and let denote the o-filter of open neighbourhoods of in the topology (in other words, ). For
a filter on and , let be the trace of on , in other words the family . Notice that is a proper filter (i.e. does not contain ) if and only if , and similarly for .
If is a topology on and , let denote the topology which has as a subbasis.
Good, McIntyre and Watson proved the following result in [3]:
Let . Then .
Conversely, if can be realized as an interval between (resp. , ) topologies, then it can be realized by a set and (resp. , ) topologies and of this form.
Suppose that is a finite partially ordered set, and . Let and be as above. Put . Then and for . Thus has the form required by Lemma 1 to ensure that .
Thus, to show that can be realized, it is enough to show that can be realized for some containing . We will show in the next section that, for every , can be realized as an interval between topologies.
Now, for each , , so is compatible with . However, is too small to be an ultrafilter subbasis, so there exist disjoint sets and which are compatible with . Put . Since is too small to be an ultrafilter subbasis, there exist disjoint sets and which are compatible with . Put . Continuing in this way we construct a sequence of disjoint subsets of , each of which is compatible with , as required. _
Throughout this section, will denote some fixed finite set, and , ordered by reverse inclusion. We will construct sets and ultrafilters as in Lemma 1 to show that can be realized as an interval between topologies.
For each , let . Let , and be as in Lemma 2. Let be a bijection. For each , and let and let be a free ultrafilter extending . Let be a uniform ultrafilter on (in other words, an ultrafilter extending the co- filter on ). Let be some point which is not an element of . For and , let (the “last” element of the sequence ), and let . For let be the set of covers of in .
We will specify a topology on by specifying a weak neighbourhood system for , in other words a collection of subsets of containing for each , such that a subset of is open if and only if for every there is some with .
For , let .
For (where ), let , where
Finally, let , where
It is easy to see that all the families are closed under finite intersections, so forms a weak neighbourhood system for a topology on . It is also clear that for each , .
For each (where ), let , where . We will prove by induction on that can be covered by a disjoint family of open sets such that . The base step is trivial, since contains only isolated points. So suppose the result holds for all , and that . For each let Then , and is open. It remains only to show that these sets are disjoint. So let and be distinct elements of , and suppose that . Then we must have and , so for some and some , and similarly for some and some , . By inductive hypothesis, then, we must have , so . But these sets are disjoint, unless , in which case , a contradiction.
Now let and be distinct elements of . Without loss of generality we assume that . We will consider separately two cases, depending on whether or not .
To complete the proof that is a topology, we must show that we can separate from any other element of . So let . If then (since in for all , and , is open, so and are separated by the disjoint open sets and . So suppose that . Let . Let and let Then and are disjoint open sets separating and . _
If we then take then will be the open set we require.
So, suppose we have chosen satisfying (1)-(3), and we wish to choose . For let . Let . Then, since , . For each choose with . Let Then, since is in for each , . Put . Then , so . Finally, suppose that and . Then , so and . Thus and , so , as required. _ Thus, putting , we have that is isomorphic to , as claimed. Now, since any finite partial order can be embedded in an order of the form (ordered by reverse inclusion) for some finite set , we have proved the following:
The construction given in this paper shows that any finite distributive lattice can be realized as an interval between topologies on a set of size . It clearly does not yield a regular topology: the closure of any neighbourhood of will contain co- many elements of each , not just many. Two obvious directions for possible improvements on this result are to ask for more separation on the topologies or to ask for smaller sets.
In [3] it is shown that the distributive lattice cannot be realized as an interval between topologies on a countable set. The question remains whether this lattice can be realized as an interval between topologies on a countable set, and whether it can be realized as an interval between topologies on some set without assuming the existence of a measurable cardinal.
The work presented in this paper is one outcome of a mini workshop organised by the Mathematics Department of the University of Auckland in April 1996. The first author would like to acknowledge the financial assistance of the Mathematics Department of Auckland University, without which his attendance would not have been possible. The second author was present on a Royal Society Postdoctoral Fellowship. These authors wish to sincerely thank the Mathematics Department for their warm hospitality.
[1] Birkhoff, G., On the combination of topologies, Fund. Math. 26 (1936), 156-166.
[2] Comfort, W.W. & Negrepontis, S., The theory of ultrafilters, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1974.
[3] Good, C., McIntyre, D.W. & Watson, W.S., Measurable cardinals and finite intervals between Hausdorff topologies, University of Auckland Mathematics Department Report Series 334, March 1996.
[4] Larson R.E. & Andima S.J., The lattice of topologies: a survey, Rocky Mountain J. Math., 5 (1975), 177-198.
[5] Rosický, J., Modular, distributive and simple intervals of the lattice of topologies, Arch. Math. Brno 11 (1975), 105-114.
[6] Vaughan, J., Small uncountable cardinals and topology, in: G.M. Reed and J. van Mill, eds., Open Problems in Topology (North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1990) 195-218.
[7] Valent, R & Larson, R.E., Basic intervals in the lattice of topologies, Duke Math. J. 39 (1972), 401-411.